A graph is said to arrow the graphs and , written , if every red-blue coloring of results in a red or a blue . The primary question has been determining graphs for which . If we consider the version for which , then we can ask a different question: Given a graph , can we determine all graphs such that , or simply ? We call this set of graphs the down-arrow Ramsey set of , or . The down-arrow Ramsey set of cycles, paths, and small complete graphs are determined. Graph ideals and graph intersections are introduced and a method for computing down-arrow Ramsey sets is described.
1. Introduction
In this paper we are only concerned with simple undirected graphs
with finite number of vertices. We follow [1] for all notation not described here. As usual,
the complete graph on vertices is
denoted , and the complete
bipartite graph whose partite sets have order and is denoted . We use the notation to mean the graph obtained
from by adding an edge
between the vertices in the partite set of order . For two graphs and , the union of and , denoted , is the graph with and . For some , the union of copies of a graph is denoted . The join of two graphs and , written , is the graph obtained from by adding all edges between
vertices of and vertices of .
We are mostly concerned with colorings of the edges of a graph using
two colors. We follow the convention that the two colors used are red
and blue and refer to such colorings as red-blue colorings of . Given a red-blue coloring of , the graphs induced by the red and blue
edges are denoted and , respectively.
A graph is said to
arrow the graphs and
, denoted if every red-blue
coloring of has the property that
either is isomorphic to a
subgraph of or is isomorphic to a subgraph of . The Ramsey number of and , denoted , is the smallest positive integer
for which . The existence of
such a number is guaranteed by the classical result of Frank
Ramsey [2]. The Ramsey
number just described is referred to as a Classical Ramsey Number and
has been extensively studied. As well, a number of variations of the
topic have been introduced (see [3] for a dynamic survey of Ramsey theory by
Radzisowski).
Of particular interest in Ramsey theory are the diagonal Ramsey
numbers, that is, Ramsey numbers of the form for a graph . It is well known that , and Greenwood and Gleason
proved in 1955 [4]. The Ramsey number is, at the date of this
writing, still unknown. However, it is known that (see [5] and [6] for the lower and upper bounds
respectively). While we offer no new bounds on this Ramsey number, we
introduce a concept in order to approach diagonal Ramsey numbers from a
new perspective.
Here, rather than find the smallest integer for which , we instead fix a
graph and find all graphs for which , or simply . For example, it is known
that [7]. It follows that every
red-blue coloring of contains a
monochromatic . As well, . So, every red-blue coloring
of contains a monochromatic
. Of course, all subgraphs of
and must also appear in either the red or
blue subgraph in any coloring of . We ask the question: Is this a
complete list? What graphs, that do not fit into common families of
graphs covered by the Radzisowski survey, are missing when we consider
every red-blue coloring of ? We
approach this problem through the lens of order theory by first
considering the partially ordered set (poset) of graphs which are
subgraphs of some graph . This
generalizes the work of Steinbach [8] who determined the poset of graphs
for when . See also [9] for this poset when .
We determine the down-arrow Ramsey set for several classes of graphs
, in particular, when is a cycle or a path of any order and
when is a complete graph of order
. As a consequence of our
results for complete graphs, we have determined all graphs with Ramsey
number at most for all .
2. The Down-Arrow Ramsey Set
of a Graph
For a fixed graph , we define
the down-arrow Ramsey set of , denoted , as the set of graphs for which . that is,
From this definition, the connection to traditional Ramsey theory is
immediate.
Observation 1. Let be a graph without isolated vertices.
Then, if and only if is the smallest positive integer for
which .
Additionally, some properties of inclusion follow from the definition
of the down-arrow Ramsey set.
Observation 2. If , then .
Observation 3. If , then for all .
Observation 3 offers a method for describing the
down-arrow Ramsey set. that is, we identify the maximal elements of
so that all elements
of the set are guaranteed to be subgraphs of one of the maximal
elements. Hence, we borrow language from order theory in order to
formalize this idea. Given a graph , let be the set of all
isomorphism classes of graphs which are subgraphs of . This set forms a partially ordered set
under the relation “is isomorphic to a subgraph of”, which we denote
““. Now, if is a graph of order , then , and hence . Noting Observation 3, we see that
is downwardly
closed. Further, any two graphs
and in have a common supergraph
in , namely . This establishes the following
observation.
Observation 4. The partially ordered set is an order ideal of the
partially ordered set .
Being the smallest poset that contains , is called the principle ideal generated , which we refer to as a graph
ideal. So, we can describe as a union of graph ideals. However, the use of order theory
here is not superficial. Our main method for determining the down-arrow
Ramsey set relies on viewing red-blue colorings of a graph as unions of
graph ideals.
Observation 5. If is a red-blue coloring of a
graph , with red subgraph and blue subgraph , then .
In determining , it
is necessary to consider multiple red-blue colorings of a graph . The following observation comes from
applying Observation 5 to more than one red-blue coloring of
. Notice here that we can think of
a coloring as the union
of ideals generated by its red and blue subgraphs, i.e.
Observation 6. Suppose are
red-blue colorings of the graph ,
in which each
decomposes into and . Then
In fact, even more can be said. If we take as our collection of
colorings the set of all red-blue colorings of , then this intersection is exactly
. Indeed, if a graph
is not in , then there must be some
coloring for which
and
. This
establishes the following proposition.
Proposition 1. Given a nonempty graph on vertices, there exists a finite set set of colorings of for which
Proposition 1 reveals that we need only develop an
efficient method for reducing intersections of graph ideals as unions of
graph ideals. However, the set of all red-blue colorings can be quite
large, even for small order graphs, and so it would be computationally
difficult to consider all of them. Instead, for a given graph we seek to determine a small number of
colorings of for which an
application of Proposition 1 reveals
exactly . However, this
implies that we must first find the maximal elements of through traditional means.
The main use for Proposition 1 is then to
show that we have actually identified the maximal elements, that is,
that there are no other elements in .
With these considerations, it was necessary to develop a rigorous
method for determining graph ideal intersections by hand. Some ideal
intersections are obvious, while others require more work. Most
intersections used in this paper can be approached by drawing Hasse
diagrams, an example of which is shown below. In more general
situations, such as ,
explanations are given for the non-trivial intersections used and are
presented as lemmas. The following observation is useful for simplifying
graph ideal intersections.
Proposition 2. Let and be graphs with . Then
Next, we see an example of how Hasse diagrams may be used to compute
intersections of specific graphs. This is a convenient point to mention
that in the determination of graph ideal intersections we do not write
the isolated vertices in any ideal intersection. Since all red-blue
colorings are of a particular graph, in the next example , it may be assumed that all graphs
have the same number of vertices as the host graph.
Example 1. We determine the graph ideal
intersections below.
Here, is the fan graph
on 6 vertices obtained by joining a vertex to a . Equivalently, .
In each of the following diagrams, let double arrows represent
vertex-deleted subgraphs, single arrows represent edge-deleted
subgraphs, and dashed lines indicate a graph in the Hasse diagram where
a subgraph of the arrow’s tail appears.
Figure 1: Diagrams Demonstrating (1) – (6)
As depicted in the diagram (a), we can determine intersection (1) by
first writing . Since
has only vertices while has 6, we are able to consider
vertex-deleted subgraphs of and be sure that no
intermediate graphs will be subgraphs of . Up to isomorphism, there are only
two options for these vertex-deleted subgraphs. Both resulting subgraphs
are subgraphs of . Since is also a subgraph of , it is clear that this
intersection is generated by . In diagrams (b) and (c) and
(d), we follow a similar process. Diagrams (b) and (c) show that we can
determine multiple intersections with the same diagram. Care must be
taken in diagram (c) since we use both vertex- and edge-deleted
subgraphs. Generally, we consider vertex-deleted subgraphs until the
order of the subgraphs match the order of the graph with which we are
intersecting. We then consider edge-deleted subgraphs.
3. The Down-Arrow
Ramsey Sets of Paths and Cycles
In this section, we determine the down-arrow Ramsey sets of cycles
and paths. First we consider cycles of even order.
Theorem 7. The down-arrow Ramsey set for all even .
Proof. First, consider the red-blue coloring of for which the red and blue subgraphs
are both . Thus,
if , then
.
Additionally, consider the red-blue coloring of the edges of such that both the red and blue
subgraphs are disjoint
copies of . This implies that if
, then . Therefore,
if , then these
two requirements imply that in fact .
Now, we show that . Let there be any red-blue coloring of
. Then, there must be at least
edges of the same
color. Say there are blue edges. Then at least of these edges
are independent, which implies that there are at least independent blue edges. Therefore, we have a
monochromatic .
Next, we determine for odd , which
proves more difficult than even .
We consider the case when
separately.
Proposition 3. The down-arrow Ramsey set .
Proof. Suppose there is a red-blue coloring of whose color classes are and . Since has 3 edges, it follows that some
color class has at least two edges. Without loss of generality, assume
that has two edges. Then we
have two adjacent red edges, hence a red . This shows . For the reverse inclusion, let . The red-blue
coloring of with as the red subgraph and as the blue subgraph shows that
either or . Hence, .
Now, we show that and are in the
down-arrow Ramsey set of all odd cycles of order .
Lemma 1. For all odd , .
Proof. It follows from a similar argument from above that
for odd as well.
To show that must be in , we consider two cases,
depending on the order of
modulo 4.
Case 1: Suppose , for . Note that in this
case, so we are aiming to show that . Let there be a red-blue
coloring of . We know that there
are at least edges of one color. Without loss of generality, say
there are at least blue edges.
Of these blue edges, at least
of them are independent. Let be a set of independent blue edges.
Since the independence number of is , then we
know there are at most
independent blue edges. Hence, there are at least two blue edges that
are adjacent to each other. Label these edges as and , and label the other edges adjacent to
and to be and respectively. Notice that at most two
of the four edges , , ,
are in the set of independent
blue edges. Thus, if , then
there are still at least
independent blue edges that are not , , , or . Therefore these independent edges
together with and form a blue . If , then we have formed a blue with edges and , which follows the statement of the
lemma.
Case 2: Suppose , for . Here we have in this
case, so we need to show that . Let there be a red-blue coloring of
. We must have at least edges of
one color, say blue. Of these blue edges, we have that at least of them are independent and at most
of
them are independent.
Notice that if there are at least independent blue edges, then we could
use the same argument in the previous case to show that there must be a
blue . Assume that
there are exactly independent blue edges, and let be
the set of all independent blue edges. Since there are at least blue edges, this means that there
are at least blue edges that
are adjacent to one or more blue edges in . It follows that there must be at least
one blue edge that is adjacent to exactly one edge
in . Call this edge , and suppose it is adjacent to , . Thus, the set of edges forms a blue and and together form a blue . Therefore, we have a blue .
Using three red-blue colorings of an odd cycle and intersections of
the ideals generated by their red and blue subgraphs, we show that any
graph in the down-arrow Ramsey set of an odd cycle must be a subgraph of or to finish the following theorem. In order to justify the
graph ideal intersection used in the proof of the theorem, we present
the following two lemmas.
Lemma 2. Let be an odd positive integer, then
Proof. Let and . It is clear that the reverse inclusion holds. For the
forward inclusion, let and notice that the edge
independence number of is . Hence, the edge independence number of
is at most . Since is also a subgraph of it follows that is a subgraph of or a
subgraph of . Since is a subgraph of the latter graph, the
result holds.
Lemma 3. Let be an odd positive integer, then
.
Proof. Let and . It is clear that the reverse inclusion holds. For the
forward inclusion, we consider two cases depending on whether or .
Case 1: Suppose , for . In this case and . Notice that deleting
any edge of yields either or and that each of these
is a subgraph of , while
itself is not. Finally, notice
that and when
.
Case 2: Suppose , for . In this case and . Hence, and so . However, and . Since , the
result holds here as well.
Theorem 8. The down-arrow Ramsey set for all odd .
Consider the following three red-blue colorings of :
:,
:,
:,
Notice first that , , and Hence, for odd ,
Finally, notice that when is
odd, .
By using a similar argument as was used for cycles, we can see that
there must be a monochromatic in every red-blue coloring of . This tells us that . In fact, we can also show that
anything in the down-arrow Ramsey set of must be in , giving us the following result.
Proposition 4. The down-arrow Ramsey set for all .
Proof. We can see that . Now, let be a graph
in the down-arrow Ramsey set of . We will use two red-blue colorings
of to show .
For ease of notation, let and .
Consider the red-blue coloring of the edges of for which the red subgraph is and the blue subgraph is
. This implies that . Additionally,
consider the red-blue coloring of the edges of for which the red subgraph is and the blue subgraph is
. This coloring suggests that
we also have .
Hence,
.
Therefore we have .
4. The Down-Arrow
Ramsey Sets of Complete Graphs
In this section, we investigate the down-arrow Ramsey sets of
complete graphs up to order 8. This section has the most connection to
traditional Ramsey theory. Recall that in calculating the down-arrow
Ramsey set of , we are able to
describe all graphs for which
for .
Since there are no nonempty proper subgraphs of , we observe the following:
Observation 9. The down-arrow Ramsey set .
Since , we already know
that the down-arrow Ramsey set from Lemma 3. Next, we
consider the complete graph on four vertices.
Proposition 5. The down-arrow Ramsey set .
Proof. By Proposition 3 it follows that
. To see the reverse inclusion, consider the following two
red-blue colorings of the edges of .
,
So, Thus, , as desired.
Proposition 6. The down-arrow Ramsey set .
Proof. We first show that . Assume to the contrary that there is a
red-blue coloring of that
avoids a monochromatic . Label
the vertices of by and . By Proposition 5, we are
guaranteed a monochromatic . So,
we may assume that and are red edges. If any of the edges
,, , or are red, then we have a red . Hence, each of these edges is blue.
However, then
is a blue . So, we have that
and hence
.
To see the reverse inclusion, consider the following red-blue
colorings of the edges of :
,
So, Thus, , as desired.
The determination of the down-arrow Ramsey sets for thus far have been fairly
straight-forward. However, the determination of the next two down-arrow
Ramsey sets, and
, are more
involved.
Lemma 4. and . In other words, .
Proof. Clearly, since the Ramsey number . To see that , first
note that
since [7].
Now, suppose that there is a red-blue coloring of that avoids a monochromatic . We know that there must be a
monochromatic , so let be a red . All edges between and must be blue, else there
would be a red . However, now the
blue subgraph is isomorphic to , which contains .
Thus, .
Theorem 10. The down-arrow Ramsey set of .
Proof. Due to Lemma 4, we need only
show that . So, consider the
following four red-blue colorings of the edges of :
Figure 2: The Red and Blue Subgraphs that Arise
from
We will show that the intersection of these four colorings is . First, using Example 1, we take
the intersection of
and to obtain the
following.
Next, we take the intersection of and and use Observation 2 to reduce. Finally, we find the
intersection of and using Example 1 and Observation 4. Notice here that and that .
Hence,
Next, we will show that the ideals generated by the three graphs in
Figure 3 make up the down-arrow Ramsey set
of .
Figure 3: Graphs that Generate
For ease of notation, we label the vertices of from the set for each of the
following lemmas. Additionally, we will use solid line segments to
represent red edges and dashed line segments to represent blue edges in
the figures that follow.
Lemma 5. Let be the graph obtained by adding two
pendent edges to the same vertex of a four-cycle as in Figure 2. Then .
Proof. Assume to the contrary that there exists a red-blue
coloring of that avoids a monochromatic . Since it is impossible to have a
3-regular graph of order 7, we know there must be a monochromatic . Say there is a red subgraph
isomorphic to in the
coloring . Let the
vertices of this subgraph be labeled as shown in Figure 3. Consider another
vertex, . Notice that can be adjacent to at most one of the
vertices with a
red edge, else a red will be
formed. Thus, must be connected
to at least three of with blue edges. Without loss of generality, assume edges
are blue. By
the same argument, we know that
must also be adjacent to at least three of with blue edges as
well. We consider two cases.
Case 1. The edges are blue. There is a blue formed, . Since the
edges and are also blue, then the following
edges must be red to avoid a blue : , , , . However, this produces a red
.
Figure 4: Forced Rd-Blue Colorings in Case 1 of Lemma 5
Case 2: The edges are blue. Again, we have formed a
blue , . Since the
edges and are also blue, then the following
edges need to be red: , , , .
Figure 5: Forced Red-Blue Colorings in Case 2 of Lemma 5
Notice that if either are red, then the edges and would form a red . Thus, they must both be blue.
However, if they are both blue, then there will be a blue .
Thus, no red-blue coloring of the edges of that avoids a monochromatic exists.
Lemma 6. Let be a triangle with a pendent edge as
in Figure 3. Then .
Proof. Assume to the contrary that there exists a red-blue
coloring of the edges
of that avoids a monochromatic
. Since the Ramsey number , we know that there must be
a monochromatic triangle in . Assume without loss of
generality that there is a red triangle, with vertices , , and . Since avoids a red , then all edges between and must be blue.
Furthermore, all edges between the vertices in will be red, else
there will be a blue . However,
this then forms a red , which
clearly has a red as a
subgraph. Hence, all red-blue colorings of the edges of must have a monochromatic .
Lemma 7. .
Proof. Again, let’s assume that there exists a red-blue
coloring of the edges
of that avoids a monochromatic
. Since there must be a
monochromatic triangle, let’s assume that it is red and it has vertices
labeled , , and . This time, all edges between the
vertices in the set must be blue to avoid a red . This creates several blue
triangles, one of which is formed between , , and . Thus, the edges , , and must be red. Similarly, , , and form a blue triangle, so the edges
, , and must also be red. However, this
forces a red .
Figure 6: Forced Red-Blue Colorings in the Proofs of Lemmas 6 and 7 respectively
The above lemmas show that . Refer to the graphs and as depicted in Figure 7 in the following proof to show the
reverse inclusion.
Figure 7: Two Graphs Used in the Proof of Theorem
11
Theorem 11. The down-arrow Ramsey set .
Proof. Consider the following five colorings of :
,
,
,
See Figure 8.
,
Figure 8: The Red and Blue Subgraphs that Arise
from
We now determine the intersection of these colorings by following
Example 1 and Observation 2. First, we compute the
intersection of colorings and . We now find the intersection of and . The relevant intersections
are computed below.
Hence, we have the following intersection. Now we
take (2) and intersect with after noting the following
intersections.
The intersection follows. Finally, we take the intersection of (3) and
.
Thus, we have our final intersection. Hence, , and we have
.
5. Further Research
There are a number of directions that research in this topic can go.
The most obvious is to determine for larger values of . Other developments in this area may
arise from one of the following pursuits.
Develop new computational methods for computing intersections of
ideals.
Consider multi-color Ramsey numbers.
Study minimal sets of colorings needed to determine a down-arrow
Ramsey set.
Let’s consider this last suggestion in more detail. By Proposition 1, we know there exists a finite set of
colorings which, when combined properly through graph ideal
intersections, give the down-arrow Ramsey set for any graph . However, it is not computationally
feasible to compute the graph ideal intersections for all colorings of a
graph. Hence, further research will be devoted to finding small sets of
colorings that determine the down-arrow Ramsey set, that is, collections
of colorings that satisfy the conclusion of Proposition 1. To this end, we define the following
terminology. Let be a nonempty
graph of order . A set of
colorings satisfying
the conclusion of Proposition 1 will be
referred to as a Ramsey elimination set. A Ramsey elimination
set of minimum cardinality is called a minimum Ramsey elimination
set. The cardinality of a minimum Ramsey elimination for is called the Ramsey elimination
number of and is denoted
.
From this definition, there are several problems one can investigate.
We identify perhaps the most fruitful here.
Problem 1. For a given graph , find properties that a minimum Ramsey
elimination set must possess. Determine if a set of colorings is a
Ramsey elimination set for
without knowing a
priori.
A solution or partial solution to the previous problem will be useful
in reducing the field of possible sets of colorings. It may then be
computationally feasible to determine the graph ideal intersections.
Some work has been done to attack this problem, in particular, we
compute and give a minimum
Ramsey elimination set for some of the complete graphs in this
paper.
Proposition 7. The Ramsey elimination number of
is 1.
Proof. We know that Take the set of colorings , and observe
that . Since for all non-empty graphs , it follows that , and a minimum Ramsey
elimination set is given by .
Proposition 8. The Ramsey elimination number of
is 2.
Proof. We know that . In Proposition 5 it is verified
that is a Ramsey elimination set. It remains
to be seen that this is a minimum Ramsey elimination set. Suppose that
there exists a graph for which
, then we would have that . However, since has edges, it must be that . Hence, either
or . that is, there
exists graphs in with edges. However, has only two edges, so this is
impossible.
The technique used in the last example can be generalized.
Proposition 9. Let be a graph of order and size . If for each we have , then .
Proof. Suppose ,
then there exists such that . Since , it must be
that either
or .
Hence, there is some graph in with at least edges.
Proposition 10. The Ramsey elimination number of
is .
Proof. We know that . In Proposition 6 it is verified
that
is a Ramsey elimination set. Furthermore, since generates and has only edges, it follows by Proposition 9
that and is a minimum Ramsey
elimination set.
In addition to investigating the problems posed above in relation to
Ramsey elimination sets, further work can be done on finding specific
down-arrow Ramsey sets that are not included or finished in this paper.
For example, we will continue to work on describing the down-arrow
Ramsey set for all complete bipartite graphs for and . Additionally, determining the
down-arrow Ramsey sets for larger complete graphs is an alluring topic
due to its connection to traditional Ramsey Theory. In this case, we
believe that further research into Ramsey elimination sets and
intersections of graph ideals will prove crucial in this effort.
Acknowledgment
We greatly appreciate the valuable suggestions made by Jamie Hallas
that resulted in an improved paper.
References:
Chartrand, G., Lesniak, L., & Zhang, P. (2010). Graphs and digraphs: 5th edition. Chapman Hall/CRC.
Ramsey, F. P. (1930). On a problem of formal logic. Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society, 30, 264-286.
Radzisowski, S. P. (2017). Small Ramsey numbers. Electronic Journal of Combinatorics, Dynamic Surveys.
Greenwood, R. E., & Gleason, A. M. (1955). Combinatorial relations and chromatic graphs. Canadian Journal of Mathematics, 7(1), 1-7.
Exoo, G. (1989). A lower bound for . Journal of Graph Theory, 13(1), 97-98.
Angeltveit, V., & McKay, B. (2017). . arXiv preprint arXiv:1703.08768v2.
Chvátal, V., & Harary, F. (1972). Generalized Ramsey theory for graphs, II. Small diagonal numbers. Proceedings of the American Mathematical Society, 32(2), 389-394.
Steinbach, P. (1999). Field guide to simple graphs (2nd corrected ed.). Design Lab.
Adams, P., Eggleton, R., & MacDougall, J. (2004). Structure of graph posets for orders 4 to 8. Congressus Numerantium, 166, 63-81.